The Bioregional State: Walking the Middle Path Between the Scylla of Eckersley of Charybdis of Bookchin
Entirely without my awareness, I have recently discovered
there are some uncanny resemblances of the ideas of the bioregional state with
the capstone ideas of political theorist Murray Bookchin (1921 – 2006)
—particularly in his “Communalism” ideas and ‘libertarian municipalism’ ideas. I was aware of him as a political and ecological thinker though I had
yet to explore his thought seriously until a week ago from this post.
As I discuss Bookchin, I recount some of my differences of opinion with Eckersley. Why? Because Eckersley and Bookchin are a pair. It helps to understand that the bioregional state is a middle path because it avoids their two extremes. These are the two mythological monsters of politics that people still worship: on the one hand the worship of the monster of Scylla, or, the reliance on the tyrannical monster of complete centralization (in Eckersley), and on the other hand, the worship of the monster of Charbydis, i.e., the reliance on the downward sucking whirlpool of complete decentralization (in Bookchin).
As with my separate development from Eckersley (who published her book on the 'green state' in 2004 (
critiqued here))--one year before my
Toward a Bioregional State (2005), Bookchin’s and my ideas for sustainability developed entirely isolated
from each other. He 'completed' his writings by 2006 (his death). I
began mine on this theme in 2001 after ruminating on these issues more seriously from the early 1990s. However in an unconnected parallel, we share many (not
all) of the same conclusions though from completely different
starting and concluding philosophies interestingly.
I see this post as one of a series of bioregional state comments on other solutions to sustainability. It is always helpful to explain or to frame the bioregional state in reference to other sustainability ideas that might on the surface seem similar though on deeper analysis can be quite different. For instance, I have already posted on the differences of the bioregional state from
Robin Eckersley and her concept of the 'green state.' I have posted on the bioregional state as very different from neo-primitivist deep ecologist
Zerzan--which is another parallel because, interestingly, Bookchin's political ecology of solutions for sustainability broke with those like Zerzan from 1995. Additionally on this theme of differentiating bioregional state solutions to sustainability, I have discussed how distinct the bioregional state is as a
'fourth ring' separate from the other three 'political rings' of the circus of environmentalism. I characterized these other three circus rings as [1] the voluntary sustainable localism movement (most bioregionalism--autonomy, democracy, materials change, identity change (voluntary simplicity, living and merely 'eating locally' as a voluntary decision)--in other words, voluntary depoliticized decentralization exclusively); [2] voluntary ecological modernization, biomimicry, industrial ecology, and the bioneers (voluntary-only corporate or supplier forms of material sustainability without any politics); and [3] sadly the ongoing anti-humanist neo-Malthusianism of many who say they are "concerned with the environment" though instead of acting to aid the environmental conditions or to improve them for people, they exclusively concentrate on blaming people--typically the most defenseless poor instead of the more fortified rich--and hope to kill off the poor one way or another. This idea of 'kill the defenseless poor globally in a racial eugenic fashion and call it environmentalism' is seen in many globalist's policies on depopulation. This is really the old British Empire discourse connected from the 1960s with an environmentalist gloss of its ongoing anti-humanism and genetic racism. Such anti-humanist groups of globalist elites are in the same class with many primitivists and deep ecologists.)
Similar to Bookchin I would agree, that, to the contrary of Malthusianists and their deep ecologist brethren, maintaining people in particular ecological spaces instead of removing them is the best political defense against other group's political economic and cultural forces of degradation. See the recent film The Silence of the Pandas: What the WWF Isn't Saying, on why the World Wildlife Fund is an environmental Trojan Horse and is perhaps environmentalism's greatest global public enemy posing as a leader, based on its record alone.
The WWF's ideas of removing people from the land while encouraging unsustainable plantation-ism and forest destruction, goals shared by the IMF and World Bank, push people off their heritage lands in which they have been successful managing and living within for thousands of years, as if pushing them into unsustainable feudal plantation-ism as a proletarianized peasant class is better when the WWF runs interference for this and 'certifies' it as green consumerism.
The WWF is a bad corporate brand. Please cancel your WWF membership: their promotion of population removal off the land and unsustainable plantation-ism is a further stratagem of the forces of degradation, Bookchin and I would agree, instead of the first step in protection of people and the land.
Bookchin and I part company after that basic political agreement though. So I think it is worth a post to comment on
our similarities and differences on praxes for sustainability. Plus, Bookchin and I have very different views on what might be called universal history, differences of views on the
deep comparative history of environmental degradation of what is to blame for it.
Bookchin
Vs. Carson: His Our Synthetic Environment (1962) Versus Her Silent Spring (1963)
As a quick background for Bookchin, he might be considered
the first published political ecologist of the United States, with the
publication of his book Our Synthetic Environment (1962) by Knopf under the pen-name Lewis Herber. That book was an ongoing project of research into ecological
implications of our synthetic chemical world. It began with his earlier long
article on synthetics in food published in the 1950s. Bookchin later updated this
1962 book in 1975 when it was at last published under his own name. It's now available for free on the web in many places.
Bookchin’s publishing of
Our Synthetic Environment (1962) by Knopf was a ‘non-media event.’ Meanwhile, the publishing of Rachel Carson’s
Silent Spring (1963) by Houghton Mifflin was a big media event: well before it was published, it was serialized in the
New Yorker from June 1962; then it was published in September 1963; then it was a Book-of-the-Month Club pick advertised with a flyer insert by none other than pro-environmentalist Supreme
Court Justice Douglas.
Bookchin was without such media support despite being
earlier, by a decade, in discussing the bad human health and ecological implications of the same
issues that Carson discusses—the dangers of self-regulating pesticides/herbicides industries,
rising cancer demographics, food adulteration, a synthetic world's ecological encouragement to more diseases instead of less, and the expansion of radiation.
Comparing the contents of both books shows they are mirrors of each other.
Carson died in the late 1960s. Bookchin lived on and morphed repeatedly through
his long, intellectually fecund life until he found a green factionalism that satisfied him. Though American, he was closely associated in the 1980s with the "Fundis" (the non-state participationist wing of the German Green Party decentralization movement (Die Grunen), and he even toured Germany.
Bookchin ‘Vs.’ Whitaker? Interesting Parallels and
Complete Differences
Comparing myself to Bookchin, he is more economic reductionist
in his analysis of ‘what is wrong' as well as more romantic about exclusive decentralization as bringing about a complete Edenic change. Bookchin classed himself as a more
ecologically inspired anarchist ("libertarian socialist") for a long while until the mid 1990s when
he broke with this association in
critique of deep ecologists,
primitivists, and others like Zerzan and Bey.
I have interestingly
critiqued such deep ecological primitivism
as anti-humanist—exactly as
Bookchin did.
I accused the followers of Zerzan’s ‘deep ecology’ of really having very little
differences with the globalist corporatist Malthusians (like Maurice Strong for
example), while Bookchin's critique of deep ecologists was that that they neglected to build a collective decentralizing social movement and were "too lifestyle individualist."
To the contrary of Bookchin's more economic reductionistic analysis though similar to his view of
unrepresentative 'ecological tyrannies' of states as causing many difficulties in regional unsustainability,
I consider political primacy more important in why we have bad materials and
bad governments that interact to protect each other. In a phrase, if Bookchin concentrated on the word "state" in the phrase "unrepresentative ecological tyrannies of states" and considered the whole concept of a larger state as the origin of degradation, I concentrate on the word "unrepresentative." For me, the issue is the lack of representation, in particular larger states and in smaller regional levels, instead of categorically blaming all larger states because they have various organizational arrangements and hardly all equally have the same ecologically degradative equality. Another form of categorical assumption of Bookchin is that a regionalized framework is innately more representative, when I feel it depends on the case as well: there can be plenty of examples how regionalism can be unrepresentative as well. The bioregional state's point becomes one of greater concern for constitutional engineering of particular institutions, whether regional, at the larger level, or in interaction, for greater representation and sustainability.
In other areas however, Bookchin's economic-only
analysis of what is to blame is similar to what you find in Eckersley. I’ve
discussed my differences on this point before versus Eckersley, another
theorist of the ‘green state’ on this point of her equal economic reductionism:
“Instead of being as anti-market as Eckersley (2004) [or as
Bookchin], and instead of being as trusting of state elites as she is [though
Bookchin is not], Whitaker argues for concentration on constitutional
engineering that will create a less corrupted state developmentalism and a more
representative developmentalism instead. A politically biased market is seen as
the origin of environmental degradation, instead of markets per se, so there
are required checks and balances in both the state and in maintaining consumer
choices in markets for different consumptive categories, to maintain
sustainability. Many more durable and local regional commodities are required
as material checks and balances against any potentials of larger
unrepresentative versions of commodities in their categories. For example, oil,
from once just a market choice, has become a corrupt unrepresentative regime of
elites created by governmental corruption via the artificial removal of
consumer choices more than markets.”
The origin of degradation is hardly all markets or all investments--it is typically the
supply versus demand issue: how as only scales get larger, particular supply-side biased arrangements get embedded in corrupt governmental politics and get separate interests from their consumers. In this dynamic, supply-side biased economic organizations in league with equally supply-side biased governments as a group move our material choices away from what consumers desire while blocking representative feedback whether from consumers or citizens, while removing choices instead of bringing them to market. On the local level, however, the 'supply versus demand' tendencies of suppliers and demand/consumers to have different material choice desires and politics, is easier to moderate. On the local level, this potentially conflicting dynamic moves more ideally closer to supply equals demand in material availabilities which is more sustainable though it's hardly just because of economic feedback issues: it's because of greater possibilities of local political feedback mattering on smaller suppliers when they have less political gatekeeping power because of their larger scale. On the local level, there can be a greater market and greater political input on 'suppliers gone rogue' without their political and economic gatekeeping (thus making suppliers more representative). It depends of course if there are greater market choices for consumers on the local level as well if they can exercise this power. That is why it is important to maintain a plurality of market choices: it is toward sustainability to remove larger forms of material clientelism. This avoids people getting into a deep clientelistic relationship with a singular degradative material supplier. Combined with the political corruption and economic corruption of supply side interests to remove choices, it can lead to their environmental degradation being politically protected and even unchallenged by consumers (because consumers have been denied other choices). There is more on this point later.
In short, unlike Bookchin or Eckersley, I have little
difficulty with capitalist frameworks as long as they operate within ecological
modernization and an uncorrupted state framework that helps to moderate the supply versus demand dynamics and that helps by this to maintain multiple
regional integrated commodity forms that are innately more sustainable and
representative. I argue without the (representative) larger state, any multiple regions by themselves only encourage unresolved conflicts and actually encourage people to support unrepresentative solutions to solve it.
As much as Eckersley is I think very blind about trusting a
larger state as a moral entity alone, Bookchin I think is equally blind about
trusting multi-regionalism alone without some form of larger state being addressed.
While I agree with Bookchin on the mistrust of such an unrepresentative state as a big cause of environmental degradation, he attempts to
entirely demote the whole concept of the larger state while I would say, more pragmatically, how do
we deal with it, and it as combined with multiple regional forms in a relationship that innately would
come about?
Bookchin as well as Eckersley both seem to develop very utopian
projections only instead of projects--without many institutional 'legs of development of how to get there to create it. From my reading of them, both additionally are rather fanatical about their ideas with little
respect for multiple opinions or disagreements. I think that is dangerous. On the contrary, I feel that the bioregional
state is toward a ‘polytopia’ of multiple real places with people with varying ideals and with their real
disagreements with each other as normal over what is the subjective good life is, though with
common desires for greater representation and choices of jurisdiction on the
local level as well as greater representation of these regional issues in larger
more abstract state levels as checks and balances. Bookchin liked to think that
his enhanced multi-regionalism would ‘destroy’ the larger state edifice, and saw such in terms of a pure conflict between good versus evil respectively. I see both levels as potentially
organizing both good and evil, so I see both levels working together with
checks and balances on each other’s potential corruption, providing people
with many venues of checks and balances on any power--whether a regional or
larger national state.
In this way the bioregional state is decidedly meant to
be non-ideological, institutional (as a site of airing and settling pragmatic differences), and cooperative in its pragmatism of differences of opinion and ideals. Meanwhile, both Bookchin and Eckersley developed a very isolated, ideological view of
the world. For Bookchin it was toward the regional ideals that were unable to be critiqued as equally a source of corruption potentially. For Eckersley it was
toward the state as an ideal that was unable to be critiqued. My view is that the worship of any singular ideological
movement as a utopia turns that ideal into a dystopia in practice because such followers are unwilling to respect differences of opinion. So any ideological
exclusionist plans of ‘pro-state’ Eckersley or ‘pro-regional-only’ Bookchin
might only be developing a legitimation for their own greenwashed repressive and degradative arrangements because they
both set up unrepresentative arrangements and worship only one level with an Inquisition of all other groups and levels. The bioregional state works from a support of
realistic multiple factions in any society and multiple levels of political integration.
Bioregional Statism Compared to Bookchin’s Communalism and
Libertarian Municipalism
In the rest of what follows below, I adapt a dry Wikipedia
text associated with Bookchin’s ideas as a trellis upon which I rewrote, upon
reflection, of the similarities and differences between Bookchin’s ideas and
the bioregional state.
---
Bioregional Statism – As a mix of common institutionalized decentralization ideas with novel
larger ecological checks and balances on corrupt centralism to improve both
levels, bioregional statism might equally be called a statist bioregionalism or
bioregionalism for states. It might additionally be called “Bioregional
Hellenism” because of its innate universalism in its recommendations for all
governmental structures and because of its wider cultural issues of Ecological Reformation (like the organization of the universities, our
consumption, additions of two different regional assemblies, and additions to
our financial relations). Bioregional Hellenization was mentioned in the book
Toward a Bioregional State (2005), from the beginning.
On the one hand, Bioregional statism is a group of political
philosophies that promote an ungatekept, decentralized, democratized, material
economy. This means ongoing decisions upon materials and technologies are made with a particular ecology in mind for their ongoing integration. This is an ongoing open-ended
historically changing process of ecology, politics, technologies, materials, and adaptation. The
open-ended process is undertaken and manageable within watershed jurisdictions using two
additional democratic institutions, the Commodity Ecology Institution and the Civic Democratic Institution,
described later. Build it and they will come. This is the common objective quality of life people desire: a sustainable, healthy, ecologically-sound economy. As for their differing opinions about subjective qualities of life (religion, culture, values, sexual relations, family styles, etc.) the bioregional state allows for this as well in each particular region and encourages it through ongoing migration between different regions as all regions are competing for people.
On the other hand, this decentralized, democratized
material/technological ecological economy is within a larger, more representatively
hierarchical, democratized multi-regional state jurisdiction and culture [1]
based on protecting common human universal rights across the multiple regions;
[2] combined with judicial checks and balances against any regional watershed’s
potential for degradation outside of itself as a form of cross-watershed
support against realistic regional corruptions in pollution flows that may
develop; and [3] as well as some form of [3a] welfare statism/redistribution,
[3b] disaster emergency funding for reconstruction, and [3c] wider civil defense. These latter larger issues to be decided
upon by the people involved in an ongoing fashion as well.
However, these three latter larger issues are kept from being entirely
sovereign in their jurisdiction over the multiple watersheds through four
stratagems: [1] denying the larger state any jurisdiction over regional
cultural jurisdiction (that are regions combined with the larger jurisdiction that preserves respecting
people’s rights of mobility and travel through the wider different cultural
regions); [2] a rotational management location substituted for any permanent
bureaucratic and/or representative capital in one durable region (to avoid a singular
capital region from which its own corruption of its region and a wider
corruption might extend); [3] various checks and balances on mobilizations of
an armed forces internally; [4] and the larger state being without any material
jurisdictions of ownership. This means the larger state is without larger national rights of nationalization or
monopolization in material issues. The largest arrangement for any public property can be "bionationalization" (within regions), if decided upon by the region itself, and
even then it is within checks and balances of regional private property in the same
sector being maintained since the origins of monopoly can be corrupting whether
it is called private property or public property. Therefore demote the monopoly
mechanism in any region, whether in public or private property. Assuredly demote by removing it
entirely from the larger level of state jurisdiction. These four issues help
to maintain a greater parity between the multiple regions and the larger
abstract state by keeping the larger abstract state 'abstract' instead of
allowing it to become an infrastructural and material ownership phenomenon in
itself. Otherwise, these four identified mechanisms become sources of
degradative corruption in the larger state, and thus in turn damaging to all
the regions and the state’s durability and sustainability.
Given regional decisions on material political economy
issues, the
decisions about private property or public property can be decided on the regional level in a democratic fashion instead of
imposed in a larger (changing) ideologically repressive arrangement. Ideally, in bioregional statism, the formulating
author feels that a good route would be to have private property in competition
with public property in all the
92 categories of consumptive use (i.e., in shelter; private
housing and public housing/shelter simultaneously checking and balancing
against each other) because both state property and private property/markets
have the same form of triage gatekeeping due to their common larger supply-side
managerial styles that encourage a dynamic of supply versus demand in the
frameworks of distribution regardless of private markets or public state
bureaucracies. Supply versus demand principles make any private property
regimes of markets always incomplete in providing for common material goods at larger
scales. Supply versus demand is why equal monopolies under the state have the
same triaging difficulties. To solve this, material management is at smaller jurisdictional sovereignty scales where the issues of
supply versus demand are moderated since both public and private supply-side
managerial interests are more under demand feedback parity (both economically
in markets and politically in government) on any particularly unrepresentative offerings of
supply-side groups--state or private.
Bioregional statists believe in more than these two issues
however. Additionally, bioregional statism involves a wider cultural Ecological Reformation: converting states,
sciences/education, financial, and consumptive property in a fuller institutional redesign while retaining respect for private and
personal property. This respect for private property is within greater regional support of democratic decision making
about local property regimes (instead of it being decided on ideological principles), i.e., within the bionationalization jurisdictional capacities of various regions. There is only the potential for bioregional
nationalization since larger scales of nationalization become supply-side
corrupt--politically, economically, and in material triaged choices that help to create other externalities instead of solving them. This means the primate jurisdictional rights are held within the
jurisdictions and decisions of the democratic arrangements and decisions of the
commodity ecology institutions,
per region or watershed.This is influenced of course by its interaction between what kind of people decide culturally to settle in a particular watershed over time, as well as the cultural influences of the
Civic Democratic Institution as well. There is more on these at the links.
Bioregional statism is opposed to coercive forms of social
organization unless the coercive aspects are regionalized and exercised with many additional democratic checks and balances both in civil rights and in material political
economy. The pragmatic issue is that with multiple regions, this allows for
multiple jurisdictions, and thus for people who disagree with a particular
region's policy to leave and to help formulate what they want sustainability
elsewhere, instead of remain repressed minorities of beliefs and material support. What is foreseen
in this dynamic is an ongoing open-ended reformulation of different regionalized ideals against
each other for what sustainability is, objectively fitted to different regions,
yet combined with understandable cultural differences on what the subjective good
life is for a particular region as well. What is additionally foreseen in this dynamic is an ongoing open-ended capacity for people to reformulate themselves and what they believe over time: It allows people to change their mind about their ideals as well.
Thus Bioregional statism foresees
greater checks and balances on coercion by both formal developments as well as by cultural plurality, instead of what are thought to be
unpragmatic attempts to “remove coercion” (like in Bookchin’s thought for
instance) that would or could become its own form of self-justified repression (which would only mean removing someone else's capacity to resist another's repression). To the contrary, the best way to remove
coercion is to have a plurality of regions in which any regional coercion is exercised more
democratically, both culturally (influenced by the Civic Democratic
Institution, the CDI) and materially (influenced by the Commodity Ecology
Institution, the CEI, designed for removing repression from supply-side biased frameworks of politics and material triage)--with options of leaving for other regions and participating there to avoid any generally accepted democratic coercion in any one region. The bioregional state promotes free association via
multiple regional institutions additions of Civic Democratic Institutions (CDI)
and Commodity Ecology Institutions (CEI) along side wider governmental
bioregional state checks and balances and even wider Ecological Reformation as
a wider political economic and ecological checks and balances. Another check and balance on coercion is the multiple cultural regions themselves as a lived check and balance of multiple ideals being preserved and enhanced and always escapable for another region--escapable even by its erstwhile original believers if they change their mind.
(To the contrary, Bookchin romanticized a completely
uninstitutionalized coterie of ecological revolutionaries. That has had its
anticipated result long before his death in almost complete isolation: the
first anticipated result of this de-institutionalizing strategy toward
sustainability is that no one remembers Bookchin; and the second anticipated
result is that long before his death his coterie disbanded into factionalisms,
instead of as here, in Bioregional statism, remaining tied together
institutionally in contention with each other’s factions within CDI and CEI
expressions which makes for a more durable ‘institutionalized
revolution/reformation’ toward democratized sustainability that outlasts though
is built from the energy of any individual’s more factional contribution.)
Thus there are novel checks and balances between [1] the
jurisdictions of multiple distinct, biophysically real ecoregional/bioregional
arenas of community, culture and materials intertwined on the regional level,
[2] versus the jurisdictions of abstract states that are designed to lack any
material jurisdictions and instead are designed better to concentrate on
maintaining more universal, ideological issues like social civil rights,
cross-regional pollution flows conflict management between regions in a neutral
fashion, cross-regional or shared welfare/emergency redistribution, and defense. In
Bioregional statism, both levels are required as part of its political
philosophy.
Bioregional statism opposes the common monopolized
jurisdictional aspects of both state socialism and (state) capitalism, for a
mixed economy scale and area of its interventions to be decided upon by the
specific region themselves instead of pre-ordained by utopian principles or by
a larger abstract state. When pre-ordained utopian ideals combine with either a
regional or a larger abstract state by itself, the only history can be a
repressive dystopia. This mixed economy scale and area of its interventions are
decided upon by the specific region themselves for material-technical,
cultural, and ecological integration issues, though within larger frameworks of
distributionary welfare statism and subsidization from the abstract level and
its common civil rights across all bioregions established from the abstract
level as well.
The term Bioregional statism is seen to emphasize a series
of checks and balances for solving all world problems dealing with the
repetition of human and ecological suffering in human history, as identified in
Ecological Revolution (2009). The term ‘Bioregional statists’ is used to differentiate their political philosophy from
both anarchistic bioregionalism (typically with its ideological opposition to cross-border trade; it's fine if a particular group wants to impose this on themselves, though they would be unable: [1] to impose it on all regions or [2] keep people in their region if they wanted to leave; or [3] unable to keep people out of their region if they wanted to come) and used to differentiate it from anti-humanistic deep ecology. Both are seen as politically unrealistic by bioregional statists arguing that these other two, respectively, are unable
to deal with real world larger regulatory issues of pollution flows across
multiple regions or actually only encouraging repressive authoritarian regimes
under green rubrics. However, if any of these groups wish to
formulate themselves as a faction or attempted majority within a particular
region and work toward sustainability, what could be wrong with that? Nothing
at all. Thus the Bioregional statists welcome such groups' energies to create their own different objective (material, technological, and ecologically interactive) quality of life and their own different subjective (cultural) qualities of life in their own region.
Adherents of bioregional statism assert that a series of
institutional adaptations based on common support for common civil rights’
freedoms and common distributionary principles can be achieved through
‘affirmitizing’ politics. The term means the removing of gatekeeping in all
decision making and thus removing one factor of its systemic corruption of
larger levels of decision making that decides to formulate policy that protects
humanly degradative and ecologically degradative larger scale endeavors. (See
‘supply versus demand’ dynamics as what is demoted in the bioregional state,
above.) Thus affirmitization of all existing institutions makes more
representative any pre-existing heritage or current authoritarian institutions
around the world that are ecologically unrepresentative and through their gatekeeping and unrepresentation create both environmental degradation and human degradation
that destroys their societies by subordinating the multi-regional majority
under a corrupt political, economic, cultural, and financial class that belongs nowhere. Thus the same political corruption
and gatekeeping on decision making both gives larger supply side interests immunity
from criminal charges while steering over time many other institutional areas toward supporting a
supply-side environmental and human degradation by being gatekept and unrepresentative across many institutional domains.
Bioregional statism has some close links to Bookchin’s
libertarian socialism because it constitutes a tendency of thought that
promotes the identification, criticism, and practical dismantling of
illegitimate authority in all aspects of life though it disagrees with
libertarian socialism in its desire for constructing as well more legitimate
and institutionalized forms of mixed decentralized authority on the regional
level decided upon by people with novel additional checks and balances of
institutions, like the CDIs (Civic Democratic Institutions) and the CEIs
(Commodity Ecology institutions). These regional institutions are designed to
avoid gatekeeping in decision making (see the book for CDI description on this
point;
see link for CEI description on this point) and thus to start together
an interactive process of social, cultural, political, financial, and material/technical
(‘economic’) changes in the infrastructural policy of the region. The CDIs and
CEIs additionally work to institutionalize the expression of an ongoing local
culture, as well as help to formulate it to begin with among an alienated population for cultural change. Thus
both institutions ongoingly serve in culture as ongoing checks and balances on any larger
levels of institutional leadership policy, in a larger Ecological Reformation of institutions and culture.
Bioregional statists see themselves as more pragmatic than
most political movements because of their support of multiple factions and
allowances for disagreement. Though idealists, they believe that corruption
will continue as well as differences of opinion in politics will continue, so
it is best to think about manners in which checks and balances on corruption,
checks and balances on ideological purism, and checks and balances on the
ongoing larger levels of states, on regional levels of states, and on other organizations can be instituted.
Accordingly, bioregional statists
draw support from manydifferent political philosophy and different cultural followers seeking to attempt to formulate their
own sustainable material versions of an objective good life while enhancing their own
cultural versions of a subjective good life. These are dual ideals in their own regions, and as ideals in practice they are always in multiple competition, comparison, and learning processes with other regions for having the most successful region gauged by its success in attracting people to their regions. The migration and emigration between regions is based on whether they can really
create and sustain a successful polity, objectively in material/technological/ecological
integration and subjectively in culture over time.
Bioregional statists believe that "the exercise of
gatekeeping power in any institutionalized form—whether economic, financial,
political, scientific, religious, or sexual, etc.—brutalizes both the wielder of
power and the one over whom it is exercised"—so the forms of power they
proffer are toward less gatekept forms of power that are more representative
and regionally legitimate to their populations—with space for disagreement
across multiple regions for people to leave a certain region if they disagree
thus creating a wide variety of regions with different arenas of social action
and reforming groups, combined with room for greater individualization in the
more nomadic flows between regional arenas. The point is that within the larger
abstract bioregional state there is a common civic and cultural arena that
protects human diversity of political ideas, protects common civil rights of
individuals, and protects ecological diversity by encouraging particular
regions to interlink their social relations into their own specific ecological
regional forms as the best objective material quality of life for them; without
hampering those who wish to work on specific cultural values in their own region; without hampering those who wish to work on other different projects in other regions; and without
hampering different subjective cultural quality of life issues held by
different people. For instance, voluntary simplicity as a culture might attempt to
formulate itself as a subjective quality of life ideal in one region while
sustainable urban cosmopolitanism and mass consumption and trade might be the equal cultural ideal
in another with export of their sustainable manufactures, and in another area, a
more religious monastic form of sustainable existence might become hegemonic with unindustrialized manufactures as an ideal. The variety possible is open-ended and endless for an open future in the bioregional state, while other political philosophies, by creating particular closed futures, turn into tyrannies over time. There are zero
limitations on people forming different cultural-material ideals for expressing
sustainability since bioregional statism encourages this by the plurality of
cultural regions. It additionally encourages this by its integrating mobility,
and by allowing people to change their minds on their own ideals over time, perhaps
throughout their life course or by influences on each other, with a sustainable version of whatever culture they want
anywhere in the bioregional state.
Bioregional statists generally place their hopes in many
baskets simultaneously for their synergistic effects like the below, without any
specific order:
- first, in a combination of more decentralized means of
direct democracy in specific institutional forms designed to avoid gatekept
decision making and politics based on exclusions (like in the CDIs and CEIs,
instead of in unstructured abstract ideals of libertarian municipalism,
citizens' assemblies, trade unions, and workers' councils that offer little
institutional ideas on how to avoid their own gatekeeping themselves); and
- second, the first point is a means to start on the regional level the
cultural Ecological Reformation of the four institutions regionally (states,
sciences/education/religion, finance, and consumption) as a greater lever for
building ongoing real world regional checks and balances later against the
world’s pre-existing heritage in corrupt, larger, supply-side biased and gatekept
institutions that cause environmental degradation. These regional changes in CDIs, in CEIs, and regional forms of the
culture of Ecological Reformation in these four areas, are seen as part of a
long-term social movement for regional betterment and as contributing
toward the larger checks and balances “to make a more perfect union” within wider
abstract state jurisdictional power over time to remove all past political unions'
history of being a route only of human and environmental degradation because
they were unrepresentative and based on supply-side gatekeeping.
Bioregional statism has some features of Bookchin’s
Libertarian municipalism, which is a political program developed by libertarian
socialist theorist Murray Bookchin, to create democratic citizens' assemblies
in towns and urban neighborhoods. The assemblies in these free municipalities
join together to replace the state with a confederation. Bioregional statism is
larger than this in the Ecological Reformation conceptions for changes beyond mere political institutions—across states, sciences/education/religion,
finance, and consumption/materials/technologies—and larger than this by
suggesting common institutional frameworks to avoid future
corruption and gatekeeping in such citizens assemblies via using the organizations
of the CDIs and CEIs.
Bookchin argued that a 'dual' power of regional groups
versus the larger state would innately be against the larger state frameworks. His libertarian
municipalism uses this strategy of dual power (a concept drawn from Trotsky's
History of the Russian Revolution) to create a situation in which two powers—the municipal confederations and the nation-state—cannot coexist. In a contrary
interpretation, for Bioregional statists, the dual power here leads only to
affirmitization: the pragmatic increasing representative effects upon the larger level and the
regional level in interaction, as a novel form of regional political, material, and cultural
checks and balance against gatekeeping political elites and supply-side biased
decisions on any level, as well as an ecological check and balance through regions
having more embedded ecological self-interests in maintaining themselves in
certain regions less like the larger distanciated political elites across multiple areas that are only interested in their durable clientelism strategies regardless of whether they are sustainable and durable for themselves, or degradative and self-destructive even of themselves.
Another differentiation between Bookchin’s views and
Bioregional statism concerns Bookchin’s Communalism. While Bookchin long placed
libertarian municipalism within the framework of political Anarchism, in the
late 1990s he broke with anarchism and in his final essay, "The
Communalist Project" (2003), identified libertarian municipalism as the
main component of Communalism.
Communalists believe that libertarian municipalism is both
the means to achieve a rational society and structure of that society.
Communalism (spelled with a capital C to differentiate it from other forms) is
a form of anarchism political philosophy coined by author and activist Murray
Bookchin as a political system to complement his environmental philosophy of
social ecology. Communalism proposes that markets and money be abolished and
that land and enterprises - i.e., private property - be placed increasingly in
the custody of the community--more precisely, the custody of citizens in free
assemblies and their delegates in confederal councils. However, Communalists
retain respect for personal property. The planning of work, the choice of
technologies, the management and distribution of goods are seen as questions
that can only be resolved in practice.
In differentiation from Communalism, bioregional statists
more pragmatically feel that instead of abolishing money and markets, these
issues simply be brought into a larger system of checks and balances—with
multiple monies being acceptable in legal tender and in taxation to keep one
particular currency from being politically dominant. In such a situation the managers of such a currency choice enhance the material and institutional properties of the currency choice to maintain its monopoly on exchange value (and its clients using it). In a context of multiple legal tenders, public and private, if one group of money/currency managers unfairly manipulates the scale or value of a common currency so
much as to reduce its simultaneous social function as a store of value, there
are other options of currency immediately and innately to utilize to give the consumer and citizen the best deal for store of value. Therefore, any particular clientelistic and impoverishing
stratagem via a currency manipulation only takes place because of its monopolized characteristic on other choices of currency. That manipulation and forced clientelism to use a certain currency simply becomes unworkable when people are given innately plural choices of
currencies as the base of their social relations, each of them equally legal
tender public and private. This means multiple legal monies in a market of
different monies for the same payments being acceptable, with at least one
issued from the regional/watershed level and at least one issued from a larger
intermediate cross-bioregional level (like a state government’s currency), as well as any larger national or international trading currencies removed from the
jurisdiction of the larger abstract state exactly like other material issues, placing it instead under the
jurisdiction of multiple state governments now forced to come to more
transparent democratic agreements on scale and value of their abstract money, because all people always have other options on the regional levels as a store of value if their money manipulation destroys the value of the currency. Such a set of institutionalized monies in the plural means each can be equally
used and equally acceptable for all debts public and private, and it
additionally means the trading and arbitrage of currencies between different
regions pegged to each other. It is the lack of state acceptance of monies for
taxation officially that keeps most smaller scale or even private currencies
from being stable. However, once multiple currencies are all legal tender in
even taxation, the check and balance principle of the state and the dynamic of
exchange value versus store of value in a currency (the financial version of the supply versus demand conflicts) is much different and more in parity and
open to people choosing the currency that suits them best for the particular
application leading to less currency manipulation being successful.
The same check and balance arrangement goes for markets as
well, in the consumptive version of supply versus demand conflicts being resolved. Instead of abolishing markets, this would only create a supply-side
triage bias and novel basis for state corruption in the use of public property that de facto becomes state elite’s private property monopoly in its
administration because people lack other choices thus it remains potentially for unchecked private
corrupt uses of state elites. To the contrary, to keep both public and private
property from being sources of supply-side consolidation, corruption and
monopoly (that are always very intertwined) there is both public and private property allowed in frameworks of
different material sectors (92 of them in the whole Commodity Ecology). Other
ideas for blending public/private participation in institutional ownership
would be bionationalization and public regional state investment and holding of
stocks to 51% (
as attempted in Bolivia for instance though on the more
corruptible national level). This in this view of markets or state ownership,
what is avoided is a complete supply-side monopolization, triage, and
gatekeeping that leads toward human and environmental degradation. This can be seen whether
the property monopoly is organized purely privately or publicly. On the contrary, in the bioregional state,
some forms of novel ‘nationalization’ are only built into this model of regional
‘bionationalization’ with any nationalization capacities of larger states
or abstract governments--these jurisdictions being removed. Such multiple regional
‘bionationalization’ can at most only be a mixed public/private frameworks
of property in some fashion to avoid any form of monopolization regionally as well, public or private. Such a mixed
economy-based ‘bionationalization’ is both a check and balance on supply-side
corruptions that can come from both purist state monopolies in property
(whether regional or national) or purist private monopolies in property. Instead, both
public and private property, in a mixed economy of both private and (regional
only) public institutional participation in any larger material endeavors, is required in a bioregional statistic view.
Since the bioregion/watershed as a culture (expressed through the CDI culturally/ideologically and through the CEI in
practice materially) increasingly has the jurisdiction over material and
technological applications and interactions, private property becomes an issue
increasingly based upon the mutual jurisdictions and feelings of the cultural
interactions of the CDI and the CEI. In other words the common cultural debate
in a watershed in an open-ended fashion over the dynamics of the direction and
institutional custody of the watershed/region is more precisely the debate and
feedback upon the custody of it in the citizens in the CEI derived from their
92 supply side participants in the CEI’s confederal councils that build into
each other and have group authority on maintaining themselves in a sustainable
manner. (See bioregional state blog post about commodity ecology, link
http://commodityecology.blogspot.com). Like Bookchin’s Communalists, in this
way bioregional statists retain respect for personal property. The planning of work,
the choice of technologies, the management and distribution of goods are seen
as questions that can only be resolved in practice between realistic
regional-only supply-side coteries of groups that actually handle the particular materials
and technologies on their regional level on a daily basis. The "absentee landlord" phenomenon and its degradative potential in history is minimized. The CEI encourages
regional suppliers to develop and to maintain their regional local knowledge of their own material flows in interaction with each other, to interlace their
manufactures and creations with each other and with their ongoing changing
local ecology. Additionally, the more regional supply-sided CEI is encouraged to have
interactions between the more widespread open cultural (more demand-sided
though hardly required to be) CDI organization. The CEIs and the CDIs are
additionally seen as dual institutions on the local level in a check and balance
relationships between supply and demand politically, though there is little
limitation on anyone joining the CDI, and the only limitation on membership in
the CEI is to be a creator/manufacturer of something in a particular category,
as an open meeting.
While Bookchin felt that Communalism would be a society
where needs are guided by rational and ecological standards, and where the
ancient notions of limit and balance replace the capitalist imperative of
"grow or die," Bioregional statists see nothing wrong with expansion
of scale of manufacturing or trade across regions as long as it is maintained within ecological contexts of the CEI arrangements of the regional level.
If it deviates, there are actual institutional means via the CEI (as well as cultural means within the CDI) to foment opposition and removal of such supply-side bias). Bioregional statists argue that Bookchin bases his work on eco-marxism which is
based on an innate ideological opposition between economics and ecology, while
bioregional statism bases itself on a variant of ecological modernization which
means that economic expansion can occur with the environment in mind in certain
situations of well chosen materials and processes of manufacture or agriculture while other poorly chosen frameworks can easily degrade the environment.
This variant of ecological modernization however is hardly economic
reductionistic because it argues that any degrading comes from unchecked
politics of supply side interests (political state or material/technological
economic, or in other institutions) demoting the power of demand interests of consumers and citizens, instead of
degradation being something innately to do with economic relations only or
primarily, like eco-marxists argue. To the contrary, unrepresentative politics
across a number of institutions is primate: it causes degradation and corrupted market relations by protecting
supply-side consolidated degradation from any feedback from
citizens and consumers, whether by gatekeeping or by repressive violence of
exclusion of their voices in states, in educational settings, in consumptive arenas, or in financial services. So political participation and removal of gatekeeping and corruption in many institutions (see
Ecological Reformation) is crucial in sustainability. Corruption creates degradation by making a degradative policy and developmental process be enhanced and protected from critique. Greater representation in institutions creates sustainability.
Bookchin, who was once renowned as an influential thinker of
social
anarchism for much of his life, beginning in 1995, became increasingly
critical of political anarchism, and in 1999 took a decisive stand against
anarchist ideology. He came to recognize his political beliefs as a genuinely
new form of
libertarian socialism, and positioned its
politics firmly in the framework of a new political ideology. In 1995, Bookchin
lamented the decline of American anarchism into primitivism, anti-technologism,
neo-situationism, individual self-expression, and "ad hoc
adventurism," at the expense of forming a social movement. Arthur Verslius
said, "Bookchin... describes himself as a 'social anarchist' because he
looks forward to a (gentle) societal revolution....Bookchin has lit out after
those whom he terms 'lifestyle anarchists.'" The publication of
"Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism" in 1995, criticizing this
tendency, was startling to anarchists. Thereafter Bookchin concluded that
American anarchism was essentially individualistic and broke with anarchism
publicly in 1999. He placed his ideas into a new political ideology:
Communalism (spelled with a capital "C" to differentiate it from
other forms of communalism), a form of libertarian socialism that retains his
ideas about assembly democracy and the necessity of decentralization of
settlement, power/money/influence, agriculture, manufacturing, etc.
Another difference between Bioregional statism and Bookchin
is that Bookchin argued that the arena for libertarian social change should be
the municipal level only. Bioregional statists argue for the arena to be wider
on the watershed level (in two additional specific institutions, the CEIs and
the CDIs per watershed), as well as in four different institutional
arrangements as part of the larger cultural and material nested change to be
taking place in the wider Ecological Reformation in all institutions.
Bookchin’s libertarian municipalism is seen not merely an
effort simply to “take over” city and municipal councils to construct a more
“environmentally friendly” government, but rather an effort to transform and
democratize these structures, to root them in popular assemblies and to knit
them together along confederal lines to appropriate a regional economy.
Libertarian municipalism intends to create a situation in which the two powers
— the municipal confederations and the nation-state — cannot coexist.
Communalists hold that this is a method to achieve a liberated society. To the
contrary, bioregional statism sees such developments as one stage on a
framework toward the modular state described below, and toward a more
representative state and its many other representative cultural institutions,
and as the beginnings of a slow change of feedback versus frameworks of the
more supply-side biased larger state that over time will have greater
representation. Bookchin is seen as being naïve about what occurs when two
different municipalities in his confederation have conflicts and seemed unable to solve what happens when such 'popular assemblies' themselves become gatekeepers. They are
unresolved in such a situation potentially, and that yields to degradation
continuing, as well as toward greater calls for unrepresentative powers to
decide the issue. Therefore the development of the larger state is maintained
as having a use for such confederational bioregionalism, and the bioregional state thus concentrates on various institutional arrangements to aid in the removal of ongoing gatekeeping on all levels of power.
On the point about the wider welfare state in the bioregional state, thus bioregional statism is a more institutionalized merging
of both Communalism and social democracy. Social democracy is a reformist
democratic socialist political ideology. Social democracy supports universal
legal entitlements in social rights for citizens. These are made up of
universal access to public services such as: workers' compensation, retirement pensions, universal
health care, universal education, maternity/paternity leave, and other services
such as child care and care for the elderly. The history of social democracy is
connected with the trade union labor movement and supports collective
bargaining rights for workers, though equally the history of social democracy
is connected with successful fast economically developing states worldwide that
combined expanded economic globalization with strengthening domestic social democracy instead of these being at odds. (Within the bioregional state of course it is quite possible for other regions to reject this financial subsidization association just as it is possible for other regions to accept it.) Contemporary social democracy advocates freedom from gatekeeping discrimination
based on differences of: ability/disability, age, class, ethnicity, gender,
language, race, religion, and sexual orientation. Within ecological
modernization and post-scarcity economics, the Bioregional state’s 'cross-bioregional social
democracy' is additionally pro-development, pro-welfare state, and pro-ecological
simultaneously instead of finding these at odds with each other. The more sustainable the ecology and the smarter the integration of material creation and ecology, the more scale of the economy is possible. It really is
just a question of throwing the bums out who gatekeep sustainability from us
politically out of a desire to keep people in clientelistic control via their socially
created artificial scarcities of ideas and materials.
Bioregional statism is wider than social democracy in this
sense of a secure common platform of universal civil rights combined with the different
regionalized material/technological and post-scarcity frameworks. The
regionalized democratic frameworks have jurisdiction over local ecology,
materials, land tenure, technological applications, and their integration. The larger frameworks of multiple regions have temporary jurisdiction over cross-region
pollution where the downstream polluted region has innate jurisdiction within
another region upstream for a particular damaging flow from any upstream pollution, to its source, enforceable by
that region and as back up only, by the support of the larger state. In such a situation the victimized downstream bioregion can vote in the additional CDIs and CEIs of the offending region until the degradative issue is solved in that region upstream. "No degradation without representation." Thus
cross-regional issues morph and change based on particular arrangements of offenses and are
invented ad hoc when required to address particular judicial and representational issues instead of the
line drawing of jurisdictions encouraging unecological feedback (as in this
example:
[1] [2]) or instead of the downstream regions lacking any jurisdictional capacities in the event of degradation from upstream.
The larger level of the abstract state's (revolving) jurisdiction is mostly reserved for organizing
wider redistributionary flows of social democracy or defense—whether welfare statism or emergency response—and
assuring that the regional differences of ideologies in the arrangements of communities
still protect common universal civil rights of their common peoples throughout
the bioregional state.
There is as well the right of secession as well as a
last resort of checks and balances of any particular state or watershed, though
the benefits of various links are positives keeping them together to work out
their differences or potential repercussions upon each other. However, the right
of secession is paramount in maintaining this reality of regionalism. The
bioregional state book describes some processes in which secession can occur as
an end result, capable of forcing realistic changes in a conflict management
processes of larger frameworks if they are corrupted (along the previous four
lines of the larger abstract state’s corruption for instance).
In the bioregional state, such ecologically regional
Communalism is the appropriate ground floor of the larger social democratic and
'smaller' multiple bioregional ecologically modernizing edifices, though with much greater concerns for checks
and balances on the larger level and greater mistrust for its potential
centralizing corruptions than most variants of statist social democracy has.
On History
Whitaker and Bookchin have differences of opinion about the universal history of environmental degradation. Whitaker’s sense of the state is part of the ongoing
affirmitization instead of something entirely ungermane to sustainability.
Unlike Bookchin, Whitaker argues there are “no [regionally Edenic] organic societies”—that humans
even at the small scale have a history of environmental degradation, and that
this regional degradation is both organizational as well as part of our innate human ability to network and to be
multi-regionally omnivores and highly mobile. As a species, this places us always somewhat on top of ecology
instead of within it by our very genetics, culture, physical mobility, and
propensity or capacity to change food/diet arrangements. (Whitaker mentioned this as early
as 1999 in earlier drafts of Ecological Revolution (2009). Unlike Bookchin’s
ideals that are based on a mythic “organic society,” Whitaker feels our human history is one of our ongoing development of
ecologically self-interested feedback into both our unrepresentative regional institutions and our mostly unrepresentative larger
networked institutions. This is the history of humans opposing other humans when the latter degrades the former. Bookchin
ignores that much of human history is actually regional versus regional warfare
and domination of different regions, instead of his assumptions of multiple peaceful
presumed “organic” societies mythically disrupted by a larger state. So in contrast to Bookchin who sees human history
as some kind of ‘good regionalism’ versus innately ‘bad cross-regionalism,’ for
Whitaker our degradative history is an issue of our species itself being cross-ecological, combined with bad human regions versus other bad human
regions, and combined with our attempts at organizationally attempting to provide the feedback into these degradative organizational patterns. This has tended to form a predictable patterned dynamic of multiple humans in multiple regions
effectively resisting or making more representative an unrepresentative state--or
making their regions more representative as well institutionally.
Thus much of
the history of the human species is the attempt to make our innate cross-ecological networked
capacities more representative and sustainable on the regional level (there was
“no Eden” that was already perfect) or by working to do the same
institutionally on the larger delocalized, distanciated level of human
networks. A past of stable Edenic ‘Bookchinite organic societies’ were instead of innately
mythically democratic and sustainable, mostly indeed quite hierarchal, biased,
sometimes
quite degradative in and of themselves
and hardly always being egalitarian regional ‘good guys’ in the
human history of stratification. Much about the larger state has encouraged that more individualized egalitarianism against regional cultural repressions, to the contrary of Bookchin's assumptions.
Thus unlike Bookchin argues, larger states are hardly a ‘strange
departure’ from his mythic “organic societies,” they are just a wider
institutional continuation us working out our innate external ecological relations conflicts and cooperations with each other on ever
larger levels of space and scale—just further removed than before, to a
distanciated level. The state arises out of the conflicts of the local level
interactions fighting typically, and one larger group takes jurisdiction over
others in a pseudo-functionalist fashion (meaning, doing it for itself as well
as attempting to make a more functional stability for itself in clientelism by taking on at least partially the interests of its clients despite its own
selfish interest of usurpation of its clients as well. Any larger consolidating elites are thus pseudo-functionalistic by being forced to do some form of mutual alliance
with those they dominate hoping to form a particular institutional arrangement that gives it
gatekeeping power over the terms and the gatekeeping of this alliance while providing some form of
short term consumptive and ideological/cultural ambivalence in those it has
repressed hoping to keep them disorganized across their multiple-regional
levels by: [1] some modicum of social mobility (of at least their elites), [2] some
material distribution, and [3] some (however limited) respect of their local
cultural forms, typically reinterpreted to make the usurping criminal elites
the ‘natural leadership’ of local cultural forms instead of being seen equally
as their destroyers. This material and ideological co-option of regional allegiances to form larger jurisdictions is an unstable ongoing relationship. It is a jurisdictional juggling of consumptive and ideological ambivalence of people
who are both repressed and gatekept against yet limitedly integrated into larger institutional arrangements.
The gatekept larger confederation elites hope to tailor
people in the future by such changes of institutions on the local level to raise people to be pliant, ambivalent, and unorganized supporters who have internalized the values of their conquerors instead of remain autonomous in culture, action, and institutions as political participants against them. This jurisdictional alliance is done typically with
religious/ideological/cultural appeals as well as material distribution
appeals, combined with a lot of violence or brinkmanship of threats of it, and combined with co-option and integration of regional elites into larger networks
to gatekeep against such regional elites being leaders for their own autonomous
region of jurisdiction anymore. This works in the short run--as pacification creates
consumptive expansion once more that suits many locally though in this short
term issue there is an internal contradiction in the positional alliance
between distanciated delocalized elites and multiple regionalist groups since each each want to make the jurisdictional and institutionalized alliance of
mobility and material distribution serve them the best. As the gatekept alliance tends to bring more risk and degradation over time, the alliance and jurisdiction itself is frayed. People may move to another jurisdictional belief, or elites might recover their capacities to provide a better leadership deal to maintain local ambivalence. Typically though the larger spatial elites, though greater
violence and gatekeeping of the regional feedback, 'adapt' by greater repression to gets the best deal from this alliance arrangement as it is increasingly challenged. This slowly removes the
material risk demotion and cultural legitimacy aspect of the alliance. Instead
the jurisdiction is what starts to encourage an expansion of risk and a
delegitimation of elites simultaneously, culturally. This jurisdictional deal encourages
a politicized consumptive consolidation. This encourages multi-regional
reevaluations of their loyalties and thus helps foment jurisdictional change
toward different regional elites once more. Since elites fight against each
other on the delocalized level as well, other equally gatekeeping aristocratic
elites are willing to pose as novel leaders of the dispossessed to uptake any regional people who are desperate to
flee previous jurisdictions that bring risk into their lives as merely a
stratagem to push them into their own equally risk-creating gatekept jurisdictions. Sooner or later (typically later), the
regional groups understand that only their own autonomy or a larger
representative framework with legitimate elites and a more sustainable material
world is in their interest. They mobilize this environmental and material politics
through nascent religious movements that reject the previous elites. However,
later, novel elites might be successful in co-opting that framework typically and repress people back
into unrepresentative hierarchies and unrepresentative cultural forms--because the previous movement was divided cross-regionally and was more easily demoted in wider military consolidation of jurisdiction later.
This is
a repeating cycle of human and environmental suffering. This is the typical
history of the world. However, once we know about it we have a means to
interrupt the cycle with more representative responses, in a common multi-regional
opposition, instead of merely in a divided and easily conquered regional opposition
alone. This sounds very much like Bookchin's 'dual power' argument, though it is toward erecting an even more representative series of nested institutions on the regional level as well as through to the abstract level of state instead of stopping on the local level.
If Bookchin argued--
"In lieu of becoming “nature rendered self-conscious” and raising “evolution to a level of self reflexivity that has always been latent in the very emergence of the natural world," humans created an irrational society that undermine[d] its own cultural accomplishments, impose[d] needless miseries on vast swaths of the population, and threaten[ed] the very survival of the ecosystem."
--Then Whitaker argues that in the short term of human history it made temporary sense to form or at least to more passively accept particular common
jurisdictional alliances between distanciated groups and regional others
because to the contrary multiple regional so called “organic societies” were
fighting at each other’s throats and degrading quite well by themselves instead of were living peaceably. (See
Carniero 1970 on the 'non-Bookchin' origins of the state). Such integrations however, in practice without a clear institutional ideal for removing gatekeeping, could just add yet another layer of
unrepresentative larger violence to the unrepresentative regional violence instead of solving the multi-regional
conflicts issues at all. Typically being unrepresentative, these institutional
relationships were processed by changes in human support mostly into other equally typical unrepresentative forms of
jurisdictional tyranny that increasingly lost a risk demotion aspect toward
more and more repressive arrangements of jurisdictions that enhanced risks and demoted participation.
Unlike Bookchin argued, human history is hardly “10 millennia
of pointless change.” Though it has been
similar in its repeating human and environmental suffering, one issue is that it has been getting
larger and larger in jurisdictional scales, and second, many positive “ecological revolutionary” movements have occurred
both because of such a larger state arrangement as well as against it. Both have enriched our humanity immeasurably with greater equal
human identification capacities and institutional protections, with peace movements, and with wider ethical
systems that were less limited to particular (fake) “organic societies” on the
local level that were really at each other’s throats all the while. That was an inherent deficiency or hypocrisy of them that made them easy to conquer instead of as Bookchin seems to assume them being historically aligned or having much in common cross-regionally. Such ecological
revolutionary movements--both developed from the larger state and against it--developed novel institutional arrangements like group
property frameworks or representative religious elites and developed into an
extension of our common human identity to an abstract level by treating
strangers with common ethics (whereas once “organic societies” would have killed
such a neighbor on sight perhaps). However, the unrepresentative qualities of this larger level equally has enhanced degradation and enhanced human and environmental suffering over time as well. At
the same moment it has made possible our collective identities and human sharing of identities and
empathies by demoting or at least moderating the history of multiple regional
autarky and by breaking up or at least providing cultural and institutional participation alternatives against a more exclusivist regionalism in identities. This is toward wider identities yet at the same moment it has been degrading us
materially. It is possible to fix this issue where we can have regional
identities and wider identities simultaneously within a larger nested sustainable framework.
If we are unable to do it, Whitaker predicts merely a repetition of human and
environmental suffering along the same path as before at ever larger scales
without anything being solved on how to institutionally remove the gatekeeping
and supply-side bias of the whole arrangement of inequitable political power both regionally and supra-regionally that have historically linked together to defend each other's lack of representation. This is a history of elite-to-base alliances, of jurisdictional arrangements as typically unrepresentative political alliances defending an elite's unrepresentative prerogatives against those who would make both levels more representative and thus make jurisdictions more representative in turn.
Whitaker believes that if nothing is done toward bioregional
statism and how it makes jurisdictions more representative, we can predict the
remainder of human history as a repetition of its past “trialectical” forms that only expand the scale of human and environmental suffering.
Whitaker instead of building an informal
“revolutionary cadre” like Bookchin wanted, believes in the power of
institutionalized arrangements, and concentrates his life in academic
publishing settings, curricular changes, real world material/technological
design changes, and money changes as far more important than informal individual activist groups by
themselves because institutions turn out people repeatedly—long after a “software programmer” is gone. Whitaker sees himself as one of these
institutional designers, thus a hardware designer—hardware meaning institutions
and institutional interactions—and a designer with a profound respect of both
the accomplishments of regionalism and larger frameworks in history that lets people build their own software of beliefs within a larger framework.
Another disagreement between Bookchin and Whitaker is that
Whitaker feels it’s hardly “capitalism” or "the concept of the state" that is destroying the environment and
ecology and brining about inequalities: it is unrepresentative states and supply-side biased dynamics of gatekeeping elites that are stratifying society based on corrupt uses of their
power to aggrandize themselves privately and publicly by gatekeeping against
checks and balances in politics and culture and economics in multiple regions, and by corrupting
material economics in the process and turning it to their state clientelistic
purposes by reducing our choices and enforcing an artificial scarcity to keep
people in their pointless lines of clientelism. These clientelisms are pointless because they involve us in actually circular cycles of human and
environmental degradation that destroys their own leadership even in time).
Thus bioregional statism is founded on another form of
universal history. Marx offered one. Bookchin offered another. Whitaker offers
another. You might call it an appreciation of Foucauldian state power and
supply side issues across any institutions meet Baudrillardian mass consumer issues throughout human and
environmental history in interaction: supply and mass demand in environmental
interaction.
For Bookchin, in such a municipal economy – confederal,
interdependent, and rational by ecological, not only technological, standards –
Communalists hold that the special interests that divide people today into
workers, professionals, managers, capitalist owners and so on would be melded
into a general interest (a social interest) in which people see themselves as
citizens guided strictly by the needs of their community and region rather than
by personal proclivities and vocational concerns. Here, it is hoped,
citizenship would come into its own, and rational as well as ecological
interpretations of the public good would supplant class and hierarchical
interests. Whitaker on the contrary, felt that ongoing conflicts are innate and
even better to have for figuring out the dynamics of how a particular institutionalized
framework of ecology, culture, materials, and technology should historically be changed over time in an open future.
Conclusion
In short, political philosophies like bioregional statism
have little commonalities with any philosophy directly because there are so
many fanatically abstract oppressive ideas that have been invented in politics
that all look like. On the contrary, Bioregional statism has drawn inspiration
from comparative historical analysis of the social organizational difficulties
of long term social degradation and environmental degradation as intermixed.
Ideologically, bioregional statism is designed as a check on
singular utopian ideologies since if any get in a complete informal domination jurisdictionally, it becomes a gatekeeping arrangement that is violently maintaining itself. Thus any ‘purist
good idea’ starts to create a dystopian and corrupting arrangement regardless
of their claimed origins. Ongoing conflict on ideals on the contrary is a useful form of checks and balances that preserves an open future of deliberation and institutional enhancement.
If Bookchin drew on Trotskyism, Bioregional statism draws on
other themes like cultural Hellenization. Instead of a Bookchin like Trotskyism
built into a drive of self-committed revolutionary violence run by destroyers
and mere re-erectors of tyranny, bioregional statists believe in a global
region-by-region addition of peaceful institutional and cultural strategies
(via CDIs and CEIs, and other Ecological Reformation cultural and institutional changes); they believe in
better regionally chosen materials and technologies (integrated in an ongoing way via CEIs), better uses of multiple
currencies and “released” material and technological issues for post-scarcity
economics, and believe in wider checks and balances for existing institutional
frameworks (in the wider Ecological Reformation).
Instead of influenced by Trotskyite ideas or backgrounds
from which Bookchin springs, Bioregional statism is better described as having
a Hellenization background, a global bioregional hellenization of cultural
frameworks and the slow rational convincing of people of the soundness of
adapting all their institutional arrangements into wider checks and balances
that combines a shared common decentralization of culture, materials, and
additions of checks and balances adapted to the particular area and suited to
its own pace of change for adaptation of the larger levels over the region,
instead of violently added or subtracted via revolutionary action that only
would create its own authoritarian corruption. Such a path of revolutionary/reactionary dynamics is avoided in the Ecological
Reformation. This means a Bioregional Hellenistic expansion of widened checks
and balances in the state as well as checks and balances in the
sciences/education, consumptive, and financial arenas instead of only in state
issues. It means a wider change in culture as well as institutions, and how
cultural additions like the CDI or the CEI in any region can formulate real
world material changes later.
Bioregional statism is a cultural, political, material/technological, and ecological
reformation that influences multiple institutions to be more ecologically
rational and more rational in maintaining nested senses of jurisdiction. This
is contrasted to other movements that promote only consolidated jurisdictions
(whether “all regional” or “all statist”) that bring about corruption,
supply-side gatekeeping and thus bring about human and ecological degradation
as state protected overtime out of their corruptions—corruptions encouraged
without the bioregional state.
For an example of differences of approach by bioregional
statists to people who believe in global government, other people believe in a
world state and they think that the previous levels have been rendered
pointless or have delegitimated themselves—or they are fanatical
revolutionaries attempting to make the more regional or national governments
intentionally malfunction by their infiltration. They believe and anticipate that a larger framework
creates solutions, and they attempt to destroy more than they create in this
way with this expectation. However what if they are wrong in their expectations?
Bioregional statists feel that the previous levels have been
problems only because they have been lacking checks and balances and that
making a larger world state is just to make larger difficulties with an even
larger lack of check and balances on supply-side tyrannies of managerial power
and far more easily gatekept power. Bioregional statists believe in multiple regional jurisdictions, then evanescent
modular states on the supra-bioregional level, keeping these levels of abstract
states without material jurisdictions and thus keeping them mostly for conflict
management instead of for corruptible material ownership purposes.
Such larger grouped modular states, built from different
bioregionally hellenized regions, are capable of being formed, divided,
unified, separated, and unified once more over time in an ongoing fluxing of
supra-watershed agreements with regions having the rights to succession to
show that these larger abstract supra-regional frameworks are the temporary fey
issues in world history and in human civics while the bioregional levels
maintain itself as the only completely real, stable, and ‘polytopian’
arrangement.
It's true, read this book. For some examples, see some
films about some long term bioregions in Europe that are much older than their fey temporary state governments at the larger level.
The bioregional state is featured in the upcoming book Polytopia (in planing), a novel based on living in such an arrangement of multiple real places (poly-topia) escaping from such a dystopian repetitive cycle of history built from beliefs in the artificiality of a singular utopia (no where) that tends, if applied in the real world, to become a
repressive dystopian tyranny in practice as it interprets itself otherwise. This false utopianism of idolizing singular ideals becomes its own self-justified dystopia. This pattern can be seen throughout human history. I argue it goes for both Bookchin’s ideas on one side to those who believe in a global government on the other side. Only modular institutional additions across many areas will get us to sustainability via a more representative nested series of institutions, in which the larger
frameworks are indeed there though are more dematerialized because their materialism can be the origin of their
corruption; while the regional ones are more materialized and given more jurisdiction over these issues. This is because while multiple regions are our sustainable salvation in finding multiple different manners to integrate ourselves into the ecologies at hand, we are innately wrapped up in finding solutions to potential regional corruptions and cross-regional integrations as well by using the larger levels.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home